Book Review

The progress of this storm:
Nature and society in a warming world

Andreas Malm’s powerful critique of current environmental philosophies puts historical materialism and cutting-edge science at the center of a call for militant action

See also: A C&C reader supplements this review:
New Materialism: Idealism of the Most Useless Sort


Andreas Malm
THE PROGRESS OF THIS STORM
Nature and society in a warming world

Verso Books, 2018

reviewed by Ian Angus

Anyone who reads contemporary green literature has seen books with titles like The End of Nature, and statements such as these:

  • “There is no such thing as nature.”[1]
  • “Nature is nothing if it is not social.”[2]
  • “Many of us no longer believe in a Nature that is independent of the Anthropos.”[3]
  • “There is nothing in our environment that we have not, in some sense or other, had a hand in producing.”[4]
  • “In every respect the world we inhabit will henceforth be the world we have made.”[5]
  • “The contrast between what is nature and what is not no longer makes any sense.”[6]

In contrast to environmentalists who want to protect nature, in some circles it has become common, even fashionable, to assert that nature no longer exists, that humans have taken over and it is impossible to distinguish between what is natural and what is social. The proponents of such views aren’t just saying that humans are part of the natural world; rather they claim that nature and society literally cannot be separated, in theory or in practice. “For better or worse,” writes Bruno Latour, “we have entered into a postnatural world.”[7]

Proponents of this viewpoint fall into three camps. Ecomodernists see the end of nature as cause for celebration. We should expand and deepen the process, to free humanity from dependence on nature and use whatever of it remains for our benefit. Others mourn the loss of nature but see no way out. Since society and nature are inseparable, only small reforms are possible. A third current says we should be hopeful and eschew catastrophism, but offers no basis for hope other than the improbable suggestion that rising environmental costs might cause capitalism to collapse before Earth’s life-support systems do.

Now Andreas Malm, who won the prestigious Deutscher Memorial Prize for his 2015 book Fossil Capital, has written a powerful essay “to scrutinize some of the theories circulating at the nature/society junction in the light of climate change.”[8] In clear and convincing prose, he shows that the “end of nature” thesis stems from deep confusion about the complex relationship between human society and the rest of nature.

Activists are often tempted to avoid philosophical discussions as a waste of our limited time, but as Malm writes, theory can help or hinder effective action. “Some theories can make the situation clearer while others might muddy it. Action remains best served by conceptual maps that mark out the colliding forces with some accuracy, not by blurry charts and foggy thinking, of which there is, as we shall see, no shortage.”[9]

His critique focuses on the related concepts of constructionism (nature is “socially constructed” by human beings) and hybridism (the social and the natural are inextricably combined, so it is impossible to distinguish between them). Both approaches are promoted in the influential work of Bruno Latour, whose devotees hail him as the most important French philosopher of our time.

Others are surprised that anyone takes Latour seriously. His contributions to “science studies” have repeatedly provoked derision from actual scientists. In one notorious case, he wrote that scientists who concluded Ramses II died of tuberculosis were wrong, because the pharaoh died thousands of years ago, while the bacteria that causes TB wasn’t discovered until 1882.[10] Apparently, the disease didn’t exist until humans constructed it!

Such foolishness characterizes his disciples’ work as well. Graham Harman, for example, writes: “We cannot say that neutrons are more real than unicorns, only that they are stronger than unicorns. After all, neutrons simply have more and better animate and inanimate allies testifying to their existence.”[11]

And Jason W. Moore, whose views Malm calls “unbridled hybridism in Marxist garb,” declares that even the most fundamental laws of physics are culturally determined: “the ‘law of entropy’ … is not determined by the biosphere in the abstract … From the standpoint of historical nature, entropy is reversible and cyclical….”[12]

A world where diseases don’t exist until someone notices them, where the laws of thermodynamics and the existence of unicorns are matters of opinion — these might be premises for one of Terry Pratchett’s Discworld fantasy novels, but not for serious consideration of society and nature. If all science is subjective, why should we accept the conclusions of climate scientists and not those of science deniers? If it is impossible to distinguish between society and the natural world, how can we possibly identify the social drivers of global warming, let alone determine what social and economic measures might slow or reverse the damage?

Sad to say, the great divide between natural science and the humanities has made room for such nonsense in academic circles. In 2007 a survey found that Latour was the 10th most frequently cited writer in the humanities, ahead of Sigmund Freud, Walter Benjamin and Karl Marx. That’s one reason why Malm’s book is so important: he strips away the nonsense that characterizes much hybridist/constructionist literature, and exposes the emptiness within, in terms that non-scientists and non-philosophers can follow. For example, regarding the oft-made claim that people’s views of nature are subjective, so objective truth doesn’t exist, he writes:

“Ten herders can draw very different portraits of the same goat, but that does not mean that the goat is a painting. If three hikers come down from a mountain with discrepant impressions — the first found it an easy trip; the second is heavily pregnant and could barely make it; the third is mostly struck by the novelty of snow — we do not thereby infer that they must have climbed three different mountains.”[13]

Elsewhere, he slams the philosophers’ penchant for “prose evacuated of meaning, a sludge dumped on the poor reader,” who may conclude that the entire subject is just too complex for ordinary folk. “It is not that such chunks of text are difficult,” he writes. “Rather, they seem devoid of propositional content almost on purpose, leading the non-initiated to ask whether these scholars really want to say something or are simply fooling around.”[14]

The Progress of This Storm would be a valuable resource if all it did was expose pretentiousness in academic environmental writing, but Malm does much more than that. His book’s greatest contribution is his debunking of the claim that nature either doesn’t exist at all or has been totally subsumed by and bundled with capitalist society. In doing this, he provides a theoretical framework for effective radical action that is must reading, not just for ecosocialists but for every serious environmental activist.

Malm’s alternative is historical materialism, which neither merges nature and society into an unbreakable unity nor views society as independent of the natural world. Human society arose within and is part of the natural world, but it has distinctive characteristics — emergent properties — that are found nowhere else in nature and that enable its uniquely constructive and destructive role.

That does not mean that humans totally dominate nature. The hybridist claim that nature is entirely bundled into society displays remarkable blindness to the natural world’s immense scale and complexity. For example, although human interference with the climate system is having catastrophic results, “it is only a minor reshuffling of grains of sand in a system whose vastness boggles the mind; all the rest is an avalanche of chain reactions, which humans do nothing to bring about. …

“Consider the fact that ice melts above 0°C. This relation — between water in its solid state and temperature — is utterly anterior and exterior to humans and what they do to one another…. [It is] an entirely natural relation, between entities in nature, with no social input whatsoever. …

“At whatever point one chooses to study global warming as a material process in the biosphere, one finds relations between things in nature …. Far from receding out of view, thousands of natural relations — between the Arctic sea ice and the jet stream, between the salinity of the water and the deep currents of the ocean, between monsoons and moisture, storm surges and sea levels, habitats and heat, drought and evapotranspiration, corals and acidity, precipitation and oscillation — define the phenomenon in all its bewildering complexity.”[15]

As this passage shows, the idea that the natural world and human society could possibly be collapsed into each other is absurd, and anyone who takes it seriously will be unable to explain what the world’s problems are, let alone how they might be solved. “If society has no properties that mark it off from the rest of the world — what we insist on calling nature — how can there possibly be such an awful amount of environmental destruction going on?[16]

“Hybridism denies that there is anything qualitatively different between UN climate negotiations and the process of photosynthesis, but not only is there an evident difference — one constructed by humans, the other not — denial of it also whisks away the significance of the combination. For the problem of climate change is constituted precisely by how social relations combine with natural ones that are not of their making. Without the primacy of the totalities of nature, emitting CO2 and other greenhouse gases would present no problem. When humans decide whether to extract fossil fuels or not, subsidise the industry or not, slash emissions worldwide or not, they take decisions on the material bridge that connects them to all the factors of the earth system, which then pull off the consequences. If the bridge did not span two sides, the decisions would have no meaning.”[17]

It isn’t possible to present Malm’s full argument about nature and society here, but these two passages summarize his main points:

“Nature did not suddenly alter itself in the nineteenth century, and so it must have been society that did, sending forth plumes of CO2 through its antecedent. Nature is not reducible to humans, who are part of it; humans are not reducible to nature, which is part of them; it is precisely in the interstices of that unity-in-difference that something like global warming can develop. Any countermeasures will occupy the same precarious place of inception.”[18]

“Nature is real; nature and society form a unity of opposites; society is constructed; agency cannot be found in inanimate matter but may still appear among human collectives, which can potentially target the incumbent technology that embodies social power — these are some of the necessary premises for an activist theory. Rejecting hybridism and its two branches, then, is not a matter of staking out some bland third way or middle course. It is about recovering the theoretical basis for ecological militancy.”[19]

On that basis, Malm proposes ten points of climate realism as a clear and unequivocal alternative to hybridism and constructivism, and three tenets of socialist climate realism as clues to the social dynamics behind global warming. While science has sometimes been used to strengthen ruling class power, he writes, “one branch has now delivered perhaps the most damning indictment ever to their rule: it is putting the material foundations for human civilisation in peril.” As a result, “surviving the warming condition requires full alignment with cutting-edge science.”[20]

“Some on the left maintain that progressives should not stoke panic — they ought to be less ‘catastrophist’ and ‘apocalyptic’ — but if we accept the principles of climate realism and stay up to date with the science, the boot is entirely on the other foot. … Dare to feel the panic. Then choose between the two main options: commit to the most militant and unwavering opposition to this system, or sit watching as it all goes down the drain.”[21]

The Progress of This Storm is at once a devastating critique of current intellectual fads, an explanation and defense of historical materialism and metabolic rift theory as indispensable tools for understanding the global crisis, and a call for a science-based mass movement to prevent global catastrophe. It is a major contribution to ecological Marxism, and, more broadly, to the development of a climate map that shows both the direction of the storm and the paths we must take to escape it.


Notes

[1] Noel Castree, Making Sense of Nature (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014), 24

[2] Neil Smith, Uneven Development (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 2008), 47

[3] Jason W. Moore, Capitalism in the Web of Life: Ecology and the Accumulation of Capital (London: Verso Books, 2015), 86

[4] Steven Vogel, Thinking Like a Mall: Environmental Philosophy After the End of Nature (Cambridge, MIT Press, 2015), 41

[5] Jedediah Purdy, After Nature: A Politics for the Anthropocene (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2015), 3

[6] Paul Wapner, Living Through the End of Nature: The Future of American Environmentalism (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2010), 134

[7] Bruno Latour, Facing Gaia (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017), 142. Emphasis in original

[8] Malm, The Progress of This Storm, (London: Verso Books, 2018), 16

[9] Ibid., 16

[10] Bruno Latour, “On the Partial Existence of Existing and Non-existing Objects,” in Lorraine Daston, ed., Biographies of Scientific Objects (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), 247-269

[11] Graham Harman, Bruno Latour: Reassembling the Political (London: Pluto Press, 2014), vii. Emphasis in original.

[12] Moore, Capitalism in the Web of Life, 97

[13] Malm, Progress, 26

[14] Ibid, 187

[15] Ibid, 72-3

[16] Ibid., 59

[17] Ibid, 74

[18] Ibid., 164

[19] Ibid., 156

[20] Ibid., 132

[21] Ibid., 226


 

9 Comments

  • I like Malm’s “Fossil Capital,” but so far this book is a hatchet job against all the postmodernists he dislikes. One example: he completely mis-cites Keith Jenkins on p. 22, accusing the guy of arguing that all that differentiates one historical account from another is “taste.” This is utter nonsense and unfair to the guy. Moreover, the whole characterization fo Jenkins’ account is off: Malm is citing a section of the book where Jenkins is reviewing a variety of views of historiography, including those that Malm must despise, like Derrida and Hayden White. Malm’s caricature is utterly incompatible with this sentence, for example: “This is not to doubt for a moment that the past actually existed, of course…” (p. 18) Those little details in the text that don’t fit with his caricature, well, they just go unremarked upon (to echo a critique he directs multiple times at writers whose work he does not like).

    Malm performs similar hatchet work on a number of thinkers who discuss the social characteristics of nature, setting up silly little strawmen on the way and trotting out more caricatures that prompt chortling on the part of the already converted who read his book.

    I know the guy is an ally in the overall struggle for the environment, and in no way would I defend Latour and his acolytes and apologists, but his scholarship can be fast and loose and downright bad. I don’t see how such work is progress in thinking about nature.

  • This is a deliciously polemical book, reminiscent of E.P. Thompson’s The Poverty of Theory in its sustained fury, here directed at the decadence of academic post-humanist theory in the face of climate change. It is nonetheless a very scholarly book that covers a large literature, accurately in the cases with which I am familiar.

    The comments above about misrepresentations of Latour conflate Angus’s review with Malm’s book, and so fail to address why Malm is not convinced by Latour’s attempts to retreat partially from his earlier constructivism. Given the hatchet-job that Latour does on Marx, Hegel, phenomenology and many other adversaries throughout his work it is hard to sympathize with these defensive reactions.

    With that said, Malm’s book is so focused on refuting “the end of nature” and expanded notions of non-human agency that it will read to many as a massive reassertion of a suspect nature-culture dichotomy. Malm’s retort is that fossil capitalism is itself responsible for creating the purified natural backlash that is climate change, which cuts to the heart of Latour’s capitalism denial and his particularly sloppy version of discourse analysis.

    I would have liked Malm to engage more fully with the nature-culture question in Marx, since he is so much more worthwhile than Latour et. al. But this is a book that rigorously focuses on the predicament we’re in, which includes a lot of inexcusably bad theory that gets a richly deserved mauling here.

  • Latour is actually brilliant. I recommend you read some of his books before dismissing him, because it leads you to dramatically mischaracterize his work.

    First of all, it’s important to note that Latour’s thinking and style of argumentation has changed over time. These days he laments being cast as “anti-science,” though he also objects to this characterization of his work.

    Read, for example, the introduction to An Inquiry into Modes of Existence, where he juxtaposes capital-s Science with science as an institution. The latter includes “the large number of researchers involved in climate analysis, the complex system for verifying data, the articles and reports, the principle of peer evaluation, the vast network of weather stations, floating weather buoys, satellites, and computers that ensure the flow of information” (p. 3), and so on. Only, he suggests, by increasing trust in the institution of science (as opposed to the abstract ideal of Science) can consensus be formed around issues of climate change.

    Latour’s thinking on social constructivism has also evolved. The question is, if the world is “socially constructed,” what is “the social”? In Reassembling the Social he goes into this question in depth. (See especially the section “Constructivism vs. social constructivism,” pp. 88-93.) He argues that the “construction” here involves human and non-human entities in very precise configurations, not some homogeneously distributed “agency.”

    In sum, please do your homework!

  • Being a philosopher my whole life (working mainly on Modern philosophy), since I’ve come to understand the magnitude of human caused climate change, I’ve also understood that I had to try and read not just the IPCC reports but as many scientific papers I could, and do my best not to talk too much nonsense about physics or climatology. I do not find the same effort on your side as regards philosophy. Your description of Bruno Latour’s ideas, for instance, is just ludicrous and plainly wrong (or do you also think he says there are no such things as right and wrong and that all opinions are equally valuable?), not to say that you identify completely different thinkers as if they were saying the same things in just slightly different ways. They are not. This ignorance and lack of curiosity won’t lead the left to anywhere better than where it is stuck right now. (just so you don’t misunderstand me: I consider myself someone who is definitely on the left side of the political spectrum).

    best,

    Déborah Danowski (author, together with Eduardo Viveiros de Castro, of The Ends of the World. Cambridge: Polity, 2016.)

  • I’ve only read the chapter against New Materialism so far. Based on your review it sounds like the rest of the book is a lively. I’m almost jealous of Malm’s ability to cut through bullshit — although I am less envious of the fact that he has to wade through it first.

    I remember when I first caught wind of New Materialism and thought that it would at least mean a turn away from idealism in the humanities. No such luck.

    New Materialism is burning through academia faster than a forest fire, but as Malm shows, its final effect remains an idealism of the most useless sort: we cannot change our relation to nature since even framing the problem in this way falsely posits a distinction between humans and nature. All we can really do, in fact, is to realize that there is no distinction between humans and things. This is combined with a sort of bizare vitalism that attributes agency to everything — the net effect of which is virtually to deny human agency altogether.

    Malm argues strongly that agency is a specifically human property (that only humans and human collectives may have agency, even if often we do not have much at all).

    This is plausible, although it would be enough to at least admit that if non-human things can have agency then this must be both quantitatively and qualitatively different from the kinds of agency that humans may posses — but new materialists resolutely refuse to make even such minimal distinctions. In fact, they seem to be allergic to distinctions in general, take this claim from Timothy Morton: “what spoons do when they scoop up soup is not very different from what I do when I talk about spoons”.

    Malm very rightly thinks that such sentences are so obviously vapid that in order to critique them, it is sufficient just to quote them. As soon as they have managed to understand the obscure claims of the various new materialists, most people will readily see that they are absurd. In spite of this, the new materialists are surprisingly influential among a certain layer of students and professors (Unfortunately, academics are not most people. Malm’s irritation with this fact is amusingly apparent.)

    Malm probably would not have bothered if not for the fact that new materialists are posing as radicals while actively espousing positions that are absolutely debilitating to any serious action on climate change. As Malm points out, unless you are capable of actually recognizing the specific human agency behind the anthropocene you will not be able to combat run-away climate change.

    There is a secondary benefit to Malm’s critique though: as a total philosophy, New Materialism is explicitly anti-dialectical and anti-historical materialism. Malm dismantles New Materialism with clarity and humor — in so doing, he also demonstrates the power of the Marxist methodology more generally.

    • Anton, thanks so much for this astute comment. Much appreciated. We are truly in a bad way when nonsense has become so popular. It is like we are living in an Alice in Wonderland world. Maybe the Russians are behind it all!!!!!!

      • I see that Timothy Morton went to Oxford and is a chaired professor at Rice. God almighty! The debasement of the higher learning is a wonder to behold. Jason Moore has flourished despite his absolute ignorance of Marx. Not to mention his constant whining. No matter how many sharp criticisms he gets, his response is that nobody understands him. As if he is a Vincent van Gogh who has invented such a phenomenally new way of thinking that it is beyond the grasp of mere mortals. Of course, van Gogh really was a genius and many artists recognized this. It is patently obvious that Moore and the rest of the blatherers like this Morton will never have it said of them that they were great artists. Read what John Berger says about van Gogh and imagine anyone at some time in the future saying such things about Moore or Morton. And while van Gogh’s paintings fill us with wonder and hope, making us see something about concrete reality we didn’t see before, the materiality and humanness of labor, for example, what we feel in the works of these supposed environmentalists is anger and dread.

  • Excellent review, Ian. Thanks for writing it. Keep pounding away at the nonsense promoted by Latour, Moore, and the Jacobin crew. There views are antithetical to the creation of an ecosocialist society. It is remarkable how they find so many adherents.

  • Malm is spot on. Human society has been behaving as though what it did was completely independent of Nature which it isn’t. Society has continuous inter-actions with Nature just as Nature has continuous inter-actions with society. These inter-actions effect both parties. The scale of the interactions and their subsequent effects on society is what matters to us. Global warming is a natural consequence of the burning of fossil fuels on a massive scale by human society. Until we stop that burning global warming will only get worse.