Ecosocialist Notebook
Debate

Abstract environmental ethics provide no guide to action

After 50 years of debate, academic philosophers of environmental ethics still interpret the world in various ways, but aren’t much help in changing it.


by Ian Angus

Members of the always interesting and often controversial Great Transition Initiative are currently discussing a paper on environmental ethics and the Earth Charter. A selection of the participants’ responses, along with the author’s original essay and his concluding thoughts, will be published in the public section of the GTI website in February.

I submitted the following comments on January 24.


“As historical experience reveals, voluntaristic wishful thinking — often wedded to a direct appeal to the authority of claimed moral imperatives — tends to predominate in politics precisely at times when the advocated political objectives are poorly grounded, due to the inherent weakness of those who promote them. Direct appeal to morality in such political discourse is used as an imaginary substitute for identifiable material and political forces which would secure the realization of the desired objectives.” — István Mészáros

The argument for a new environmental ethic, simply put, is that the dominant worldview in modern society considers human needs to be more important than those of non-humans. So long as such anthropocentric ethics predominate, the destruction of the natural world will continue unabated.

“If humans are taken to be more valuable beings than other species, then it would always follow that any human need, want or desire must necessarily take priority over the need or interests of nonhuman nature, no matter how critical or essential the latter needs may be.” — Robyn Eckersley

What’s needed, therefore, is a new system of ethics that recognizes the moral right of non-human nature to exist and develop without human interference and regardless of human needs.

‘Simulacra of morality’

The founders of ecocentric philosophy were convinced that they were making fundamentally important major advances in philosophy and ethics. Roderick Nash described the conclusions of environmental ethics as “revolutionary” and “arguably the most dramatic expansion of morality in the course of human thought.” That sounds radical, but in practice, evolutionary ethics has proven very difficult to pin down. Conflicting interpretations of non-anthropocentrism and intrinsic value multiplied.

The debates go on and on, reminiscent of medieval scholastics discussing how many angels can dance on the head of a pin.The philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre says that in our time, “in moral argument the apparent assertion of principles functions as a mask for expressions of personal preference.” The result is “simulacra of morality” characterized by interminable debates in which there is no rational way to choose between the various positions (After Virtue, 1985).

That’s certainly true of the debates among environmental ethicists. After fifty years of discussion, there is no agreement on what ecocentrism and biocentrism and intrinsic value and other key terms might actually mean in practice.

Indeed, the most notable feature of these debates is how abstract they are. Book after book discusses environmental ethics while making few concrete references to actual environmental problems. Instead, we are presented with “social/moral theories which presuppose a world radically different from the one we occupy, thereby rendering them irrelevant as solutions to the problems which face us in the real, non-fantasy world” (KeekokLee).

A case in point is Richard Sylvan’s widely cited “last man” argument for a new environmental ethic. Under the basic chauvinism that characterizes existing Western ethical systems, he wrote, it would be morally acceptable for the last man on earth to systematically and deliberately destroy every other living thing on the planet.

This fantasy has been justly called radically under-described. What happened to everyone else? Did they all die at once, or was this a long process? Could one man actually destroy every living thing? Why would the last man destroy everything? Is it wanton destruction, or an act of despair, or some bizarre religious rite?

Even if we willingly suspend disbelief in Sylvan’s Twilight Zone scenario, why should anyone believe that the existence (or not) of ecocentric ethics would have any effect whatsoever on the behavior of the last man — or of anyone else, for that matter?

MacIntyre’s critique of interminable moral discussions that “apparently can find no terminus” has rarely been better illustrated. The participants in these debates are professional academic philosophers using the most sophisticated tools of argument and analysis that the field has developed. The fact that they cannot agree strongly suggests, as MacIntyre says, that there is something fundamentally wrong:

“If those who claim to be able to formulate principles on which rational moral agents ought to agree cannot secure agreement on the formulation of those principles from their colleagues who share their basic philosophical purpose and method, there is once again prima facie evidence that their project has failed.”

Morality versus Moralism

In an article revealingly titled “Environmental philosophy IS environmental activism: the most radical and effective kind,” environmental philosopher Baird Callicott insists that the quest for
non-anthropocentric ethics has direct practical application:

“If all environmental values are anthropocentric and instrumental, then they have to compete head to head with the economic values derived from converting rain forests to lumber and pulp, savannas to cattle pasture, and so on. Environmentalists, in other words, must show that preserving biological diversity is of greater instrumental value to present and future generations than is lucrative timber extraction, agricultural conversion, hydroelectric impoundment, mining, and so on. For this simple reason, a persuasive philosophical case for the intrinsic value of nonhuman natural entities and nature as a whole would make a huge practical difference.”

To take this seriously, we have to believe that only the absence of a “persuasive philosophical case” has allowed giant corporations to continue destroying forests and savannas.

Imagine the president of Exxon or Monsanto explaining to shareholders that profits are down because a professor had alerted them to the intrinsic value of nonhuman natural entities. Imagine the shareholders applauding vigorously and voting him a big bonus for extending moral consideration to ecosystems!

In the real world, a mountain of hard scientific evidence, including detailed accounts of the probable impact of global warming on both human and nonhuman nature, has made no practical difference to greenhouse gas emissions. The power and profits of the fossil fuel industry and its allies determine the environmental agenda, not science or ethics.

“Lucrative timber extraction, agricultural conversion, hydroelectric impoundment, mining, and so on” don’t continue because of bad philosophy, but precisely because they are lucrative. Morality has nothing to do with the plunderers’ decisions: so long as it is profitable to destroy the earth, and there is no counterforce that can to stop them, they will continue to do so, even if they undermine the sources of their wealth and the conditions that make the earth livable.

That is not to say that anti-ecological behavior should not be condemned on moral grounds — rather, it is to insist on the vital distinction between morality and moralism. As Perry Anderson writes, that distinction helps overcome the tendency of moral judgments “to become substitutes for explanatory accounts of history.”

“Moral consciousness is certainly indispensable to the very idea of socialism: Engels himself emphasized that ‘a really human morality’ would be one of the hallmarks of communism, the finest product of its conquest of the age-old social divisions and antagonisms rooted in scarcity. Moralism, on the other hand, denotes the vain intrusion of moral judgments in lieu of causal understanding.”

Moral judgments in lieu of causal understanding — that phrase should be inscribed over the entrance of every department of environmental ethics.

 

 

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Posted in Ecosoc Notebook, Ecosocialism

4 Responses to Abstract environmental ethics provide no guide to action

  1. Ian Macbeth February 2, 2020 at 6:09 am #

    Thank you for this interesting and valuable critique. Can you cite the source for the Anderson quote at the end, please. Would like to read more of this.

    • Ian Angus February 2, 2020 at 7:46 am #

      The quote is from Perry Anderson, Arguments Within English Marxism (London: Verso, 1980), page 86.

  2. Philip Ward January 30, 2020 at 9:42 am #

    Thank you very much for this critique of ecological philosophy. I first heard of the concept of “intrinsic value” when the late and much missed Joel Kovel argued in a paper presented to an ecosocialist conference in Amsterdam in 2007 that for Marxists it should stand alongside exchange value and use value as tools for use in the ecosocialist critique of capitalism. I had not heard the term before and I don’t recall it being used in the first edition of his book “The Enemy of Nature” (I haven’t read the second edition).

    I immediately thought that this concept itself had very little value itself: it is internally contradictory. “Intrinsic value” has been invented by human beings: how a person they claim this or that species possesses such a property? By doing so, they are immediately giving it a human-determined value. And who decides if something in nature has it?

    Ultimately, such decisions are about power and the balance of class forces, not this or that natural phenomenon. It so happens that the interests of the working masses and the preservation of humanity depend on stopping the ruling class from trashing ecosystems. The productive forces and levels of production of material things are already over-developed: that is the consequence of the Great Acceleration of the 1950s. Now, the task is to ensure that humanity’s needs are met while also preserving ecosystems, which is something that the capitalist system has proved incapable of carrying out.

  3. Robert Newton January 30, 2020 at 6:52 am #

    Good morning Ian.

    Its a big leap from “would make a huge practical difference” to “only the absence of”. I.e.: one can find an important, useful, in some instances critical role for a philosophical underpinning of the rights (stakes, importance) of non-human beings in developing consciousness … without falling over into believing that consciousness per se drives a change in the economy.

    As you say, the fossil fuel industry couldn’t give a hoot about the animals. Nonetheless, millions of people (including here small framers, artisanal fishing fleets, subsistence hunters and forestry workers alongside intellectuals and urban Greens) finding the ‘humanity’ in animals, plants or whole places can become a material force through their activism. The links between moral conviction, affect and action are, I think, very strong. In fact, as an organizer I’d say that it is very hard to move people to action on economic arguments alone, which (perhaps ironically) can feel abstract compared to the emotional effects that the economy conditions.

    I recently taught a class on “diverging stakeholder interests in a warming world” (i.e.: ways that global warming is heightening class contradictions). In their case studies, three of my students linked to the inherent interests of impacted species. Two of the three were first-gen working class ‘kids’. None of them were delusional about corporations caring about the birds, salmon or forests mammals. Nor did they ignore the conflicts between industries, workers and residents. But the exercise of putting themselves in the skins of those other beings was useful to them, both in seeing a broader picture and in strengthening their convictions.

    Having watched their explorations, I wonder, as well, whether it doesn’t situate their links to ecology as one of solidarity, rather than compassion … a shift in metaphor that we should recognize from our organizational work as a significantly better starting point.

 characters left
Please be concise